MrFalconfly said:
Before we continue with this very interesting discussion (I'm being honest. It is interesting, because I get to see how other people look at this issue), I'm going to ask you a question.
Do you think a sportscar can be a piece of art?
Or is it just me being a complete loon?
As for "Every medium is going to have necessary idiosyncratic properties, whose functionality are, usually, a prerequisite to consumption". So far, no other medium than videogames (except perhaps sportscars, but that's why I asked you) requires your active participation. Your input is what completes the art. Until you decide to play it, it's a "dead" piece of hardware. And that's the reason for why I think it's so important for a games reviewer to also review the gameplay, because it is the gameplay that (in my mind) complete's the art, and ultimately makes it art.
I'm going to be honest, and say that I don't think it's feasible, in the boundaries of human discourse, to define what art is, for everyone. That being said, no particular argument stands out as to why sportscars
cannot be considered art, that doesn't do away with art, altogether, by ridding human intellect of metaphysics. Furthermore, I'd argue that any intrinsic distinction is nearly impossible. Duchamp, for example, filled entire galleries with everyday objects. Had sportscars existed at the time, and he happened to display one, it would almost certainly be considered a priceless work of art, nowadays.
For this reason, the history of art is an increasing trend towards "inclusion", where the boundaries of what constitutes art continues to grow. I don't think it's so important, however, to consider what is and is not art, but to focus on the expression or concept, as you can see it. What matters is whether or not the art is good, in other words. Indeed, the deployment of Duchamp's "readymades" was a two part process, the "creative act" of placing a snowshovel, or a pile of normal bricks, in an art gallery, and the critical interpretation by the work's audience, which legitimized the process as part of the artistic discussion. The object itself, is, essentially, irrelevant, which was Duchamp's point. Art is what we say it is, and entirely dependent on context - which includes the observer (which obviously includes critics).
Short answer - no, I don't think you're a loon.
If art is to be loosely understood as an expression in relation to some part of existence, as the artist sees it, then review is to be seen as an expression about the art itself, as the critic sees it. This unique point of view of the critic is what separates it from a mere description of the work in question, like a Wikipedia article.
If we don't expect the artist, themselves, to have some sort of duty to meet the public's preconceived expectations of what artwork should be (indeed, this would be the - end - of art), why should we then expect the critic to be restrained with such expectations, either? It's an important distinction. The role of the critic, like the artist, is intrinsic, not extrinsic. Their primary goal is to actualize their own, internal, motivations, which may happen to align, luckily, with what a lot of the public considers digestible.
Now you can easily counter, at this point, that perhaps you - do - have such expectations of artists, and their subsequent critics, namely that their work should be primarily motivated by extrinsic factors of pubic interest, but I would then counter that this runs the real risk of affirming the anti-intellectualism bias the thread alludes to. Narrowing the range of possible discussion on a topic to whatever suits your own definition of practical needs, even if those needs happen to be shared by many, is anti-intellectualism incarnate.
Indeed, who even said that there's supposed to be a line between what we consider artork and criticism in the first place? Some artwork/criticism, for example, blurs the line of what you would even consider artwork/criticism, such as when Banksy hung his own satirical artwork in the MoMA.
http://www.nytimes.com/2005/03/24/arts/design/need-talent-to-exhibit-in-museums-not-this-prankster.html
Any concerns about the review process falling apart into meaningless, should we entertain such outlandish behavior to be considered genuine "criticism" could obviously, also, be said about artwork. Art ranges the gambit from utterly incomprehensible squealing performance art to Full House. Despite this latitude, and general acceptance, no "core" of art is in danger of falling apart. Classical portraits and landscapes exist right beside Rothko and Dark Souls. There's no apparent reason why "traditional review" would be threatened by having an unbound approach to criticism any more than representational artwork has been threatened by modern art.
I think we can say that something is a "bad review", in so much that it's content is worthy of well reasoned ridicule, showcasing things such as internal inconsistency, or a poor understanding of it's subject matter. My argument, in a nutshell, is that running afoul of an individual's personal limitations they have set on what a "review" is supposed to be, isn't enough evidence, on it's own, to call it bad. You can, at most, say that you, personally, don't like it.
Going back to Duchamp's snowshovel, it's a different thing entirely to say that it's "bad art" vs. simply saying that you don't like it. Perhaps, an easier example to relate to is music. You may not like a lot of music, but that's a different thing entirely from stating that it's "bad music", which implies that others should agree with your assessment based on rational conclusions you've drawn.
Internet culture, in general, is constantly guilty of not observing this distinction, which is the root of the debate about anti-intellectualism. There is simply a grossly inflated sense of importance attributed to one's preferences, vs. the impact of making actually well reasoned arguments. Fwiw, reviewers, also, contribute to this error, which often leads to a justifiably poor reputation amongst critics.
In summary, not liking a review, because it prioritized ideological content, doesn't mean that it's automatically a bad review, even though we may label it that based on how well it's premises or content holds up to scrutiny. However, when scrutinizing the arguments made by the author, the scrutiny itself must also hold up to scrutiny, in a way that is consistent with logic and reason, and does not boil down to self-justifying preferences.
To revisit your car analogy, concerning leather seats, I'm not sure we could call your hypothetical review bad, purely for basing itself on issues of animal rights, any more than we can call my previously cited film review of the Lone Ranger bad, for focusing on the issues of Native Americans. It's a difficult thing to judge the relative importance of anther's ideology, or it's relationship to art, without proper disputation. As a thought experiment, I'd turn the example on it's head. How serious of an issue would a manufacturing component of the car have to be, before it should dominate reviews of the product, perhaps excusing omissions of things like how it handles? So long as an answer is possible, we have the thread of a potential justification for advocacy journalism, which is where the article in question is coming from. Again, that doesn't mean it's a sound read.